WEIGRATE LTD

White Paper

Weigrate Auction White Paper & Business

What is WeigRate penny auction

WeigRate platform vendor

Main reason of creating WeigRate platform and its  services

How cryptocurrency will be implemented

What cryptocurrencies can be added?

Human side of auction

Commercial / Gambling side of auction

Separated levels for bids packs and auction vale levels

Money rasing using auction

Sell with 50 % instantly

Vendor Vouchers

Buyer / seller protection

Featured services  and fucntions

Fraud Prevention

Became an Agency , world wide development

Market demand Board

Auction Math

A story...

“The banner ad says “Macbook Pro: 90% off!” It seems too good to be true, but you click on it anyway and find yourself. The prices are insane! The Macbook is around $44 dollars with under a minute to go and the other items are similarly priced. Surely there is no way a website like this could stay in business selling such high-priced items for so little money.”

-The Game-

ABSTRACT

Auctions are powerful because of their efficiency. Any sale of an item is an interaction between the price at which a merchant is willing to sell (WTS), and the price at which a consumer is willing to buy (WTP). These two levels rarely meet perfectly, resulting in consumer surplus (the buyer pays less than what they would have been willing to pay) and/or producer surplus (the merchant is able to sell for higher than their minimum price). Because the price is the same for all consumers in a traditional sale, some consumers spend less than the maximum they would have been willing to, and some don't make a purchase at all, even if their WTP exceeds the merchants WTS. The structure of auctions has the effect of collapsing these surpluses. As the price of the item rises with each successive bid, buyers with lower WTP drop out of the auction until the consumer with the highest WTP eventually wins the item.

The closest analog to penny auctions in economic theory is the „all pay auction‟. In an all pay auction bids are submitted in full regardless of the eventual winner. All pay auctions have been found to result in total payments greatly in excess of the value of the auctioned item. This is true both in the classroom laboratory and in real world examples such as the allocation of bandwidth spectrum through a lobbying process.

Competitors

On Regular Auctions, the bid increment is unlimited, so just placing a bid is no guarantee of moving into the lead if someone else has placed a larger bid than you.

On Weigrate - every time someone bids they become the bid leader until the next bidder replaces them.

Because of this, sale prices on items stay very low, meaning that the attractiveness of placing a bid does not decline very much as the auction goes on. This is especially true when the item has a comparatively high retail price. A bidder on an $800 iPad is unlikely to see much of a difference between a price of $10 and a price of $50. Additionally, the true cost of bidding is disguised somewhat by the low cost of each individual bid. In economics, prospect theory asserts that losses hurt relatively more than gains of a similar amount. When a user places a bid on Ebay, he or she sees the entire amount at once, which can be a bit daunting. Since people tend to mentally separate losses (or costs) spending $100 in one cent increments has less of an emotional impact that dropping that same $100 all at once.

What is WeigRate Auction ?

Weigrate is a relatively new auction mechanism run by multiple online companies.

A bidding fee auction, also called a penny auction, is a type of all-pay auction in which all participants must pay a refundable fee to place each small incremental bid. The auction ends after a period of time, typically ten to twenty seconds. Last bid reached auction reserve wins the item and also pays the final bid price.

Participants pay a fee to purchase bids. Each of the bids increases the price of the item by a small amount, such as one penny (0.01 USD, 1¢, or 0.01 GBP, 1p; hence the name of the auction), and extends the time of the auction by a 30 minutes.

Why WeigRate different?

Because of setting every auction to a reserved limit . LAST BID – WINS!

The Reserve Price is the sellers minimum acceptable price at auction and the figure below which the auctioneer cannot sell. The Reserve Price is always disclosed at auction between the seller and the auctioneers. Both the Guide Price and the Reserve Price can’t be subjected to change Once auction has been started and at least 1 bid placed – auction edition or any amendment is prohibited.

Every auction is settled for 10 times restart to get it’s goals. If auction has been restarted 10 time and goals not reached- system automatically disqualify auction item and refund bids. If auction item stock control was enable then auction can be rested 10 times for every stock item until some of them will be sold or wined.

That provides comfortable sales for suppliers and wholesalers.

Became a Weigrate Agency

Own Market Control

Terms & Conditions will be published at 2017 November 15th

WeigRate as a Price War Concept.

What is a 'Price War' ?

A price war is when companies continuously lower prices to undercut the competition. A price war may be used to increase revenue in the short term or as a longer term strategy to gain market share. Price wars can be prevented through strategic price management (with non-aggressive pricing), thorough understanding of the competition, or even communication with competitors.

BREAKING DOWN 'Price War'

When a company wants to increase market share, usually the easiest way is to reduce prices, which increases product sales. The competition may be forced to follow suit if its products are similar. As prices get lower the quantity of sales increases and customers receive the benefits. Eventually, a price point is reached that only one company can afford.
Companies will not be able to sell at a loss in an attempt to eliminate the competition completely.

Auction fees and penny auction price conversion.

Weigrate Vendor Platform

One of main aspect of WeigRate auction – once users will start bidding on item and some item is won – then seller will get it is payment for sure. Payment amount already will be collected inside of system and will be available once shipping documents will be provided , safe purposes. To compare with regular auctions where users can place their bids and once win – they can delay payments , or not to pay at all - WeigRate saves time and money for sellers. Once auction starts and wonned – seller will get amount.

Because of indexed auction reserve price seller can estimate absolute success of selling his item.

For example, auction has 1000 users , seller sell a computer. For 1000 usd = 20usd (2000bids)
Means every user average is 2 bids only.

Because of 1000 users will be interested to win then nobody will wait until auction ends or restarted – users will try to click fast because last bid – wins.

Main reason of creating WeigRate platform

Provide users new possibility of getting any valuable items at low price fast and legal way. That concept of getting items at low price has some other aspects and main of them is to get a huge profit one wined item can be sold with good profit.

That has to become a trending platform for users to win good items or vouchers very cheap.

As example a trip to some island may cost 2000 usd but auction target price will be converted and settled to a 40 usd only .

Make your dream to become true.

Lot of peoples are wasting their moneys for lottery, some betting or similar. Auction will remove that negative factor as money wasting op to – 0 usd.

Every auction has its auction reserve level – which is target price. Every user can evaluate his bids amount and possibility to win any item.

Good option to move and promote any type of products services on market using auction reserve price.

Possibility to use WeigRate platform to build any type of commercial campaigns and attract more users and customers.

How cryptocurrency will be implemented

Cryptocurrencies
• Wrt
• Wrtw
Will has dynamic price according to market demand indexed with coinmarketcap.com

All other prices also will be regulated with coinmarketcap.com price averages.

WRT & WRTw Value

GROWTH POTENTIAL

"Blockchain has received a significant amount of analyst and press attention over the last few years as this emerging technology holds significant potential,"

The growth of the market can also be assessed by the fact that market capitalization of cryptocurrencies reached a new high of $110 Billion as of June 2017, an increase of 1363% since Feb 19 2016. Bitcoin and Ether, two of the most famous cryptocurrencies, have a market capitalzation of approx. $42 Billion and $25 Billion respectively.

Additional features will be implemented with native WeigRate wallet. read more at…..

WeigRate is open to cooperate with credit/debit cards merchants and direct bank payment merchants worldwide. Some restrictions and limitations may apply.

Human side of the auction.

The first thing a potential bidder must choose is when to enter the auction. There are three conditions that must all be satisfied for an individual bidder to win an auction. They must have placed the last bid. All other active bidders must make a decision following that last bid to stop bidding. (Either permanently, a stopping decision, or temporarily, because they expect another bidder to bid in their place) Finally, no new potential bidders can make a decision to enter following the last bid. It would be impossible to determine, except by random luck, the exact time that bidding will stop. However, bidders could speculate as to the range of price during which that might happen. Swoopo also posts the price that a similar item was recently sold for, assisting (or confusing) this process. Therefore, a rational bidder will wait to enter until the price reaches their estimation of that range and then enter. Each bidder will have a different estimate of this range, leading to different entry points. Bidders will also have different tolerances for risk, which will lead to divergences in entry behavior as well. After entry, bidders must decide whether to bid or wait. There is some information available to bidders that may help them make this decision.

However, there is an additional element to penny auctions that has the effect of introducing even more randomness: free entry into the game. Imagine that during the course of a single poker hand a new player could walk up and be dealt a hand without matching the bets that had already been made. Essentially, this is what penny auction sites allow. Because of this, a bidder in a penny auction is betting not only on the willingness to pay of the other bidders, but also on the willingness to pay of potential bidders who have yet to enter the auction. The combination of these two elements suggests a game who‟s result is highly influenced by chance.

System has auto refund option – independent from admin or seller or auctioneers.every auction can be restarted 10 times in case there not enough bids or auction does not won. Auction will be disqualified after 10 restarts and all bids will be refunded to auctioneers instantly.

If auction has been woned then auctioneers can refund bids in amount according to a new bids pack and get 10% bonus.

Example :

Wasted bids – 50 +new bids 50 +10% of new bids
Usd has to pay 50 usd and refund 50+50+5bids
Bids can be returned within 30 days.

If any user has used fraud transfer in order to purchase BIDs, and later on has participated some auction then auction will be declined and disqualified, auctioneers will get bids back instantly with further update by email.

Commercial / Gambling side of auction

WeigRate auction is in full compliance with Uk legislation.

Whether or not penny auctions are gambling has been a question of much controversy. To date penny auctions have not been regulated or formerly considered to fall under the same category.

The UK Gambling Commission, as of March of 2011, still does not consider penny auctions to be gambling. However, they did say that they’d be keeping a close eye on their developments.

Separated levels for bids packs and auction value levels.

Item’s Auction Levels

There are 4 available auction levels and users are as well categorized according to their auction levels. Whenever a user registers with WeigRate Auction by purchasing a Bids pack, the user is by default a level 0 user. However, the user can rise to his desired level by purchasing higher levels’ bids pack.
If a user got bids pack from level 1 then he can only take part in auctions in level 1 but unable to partake in auctions which belong to the higher level (2, 3 & 4) until he purchases the higher level bids pack. It should be noted that accumulated bids will not raise users’ level.
• If the user is a 2nd level user, then he can bids on level 1 and 2 auctions respectively.
• Also, users in 3rd level can partake in auctions in level 1, 2 and 3 except level 4 auctions.
• While the users that are in 4th level can bid all levels
There are additional daily bonuses provided for bids packs starting from 1st level - $200 pack.

Item’s Auction Levels

Regarding the posting of items in auctions levels, every auction items are categorized by targeted pricing, which are calculated by formula and are assigned according to their prices. In a situation whereby an expensive item is mistakenly posted in the wrong level, then it will be automatically assigned to higher auction level.
Below are auction levels, according to target price
• 1 level target price $0 – $49.99______________(item price $0 – $4,999.99)
• 2 level target price $50 – $499.99___________(item price $5,000 – $49,999.99)
• 3 level target price $500 – $2499.99________(item price $50,000 – $249,999.99)
• 4 level target price $2500 – Unlimited______(item price $250,000 – Unlimited)

Main purpose of adding levels system is to prevent users from lowest levels bid on higher level auction. That would be unfair if user who bought bids for 50 usd only will win real state auction suited for users who has purchased 1000 usd or more.

Raising Money using auction.

Exchange items to cryptocurrency

Sell at 50 % instantly

Sometimes user will face situation when it will be useless to deliver some item from other country, or it is impossible to deliver item - as it is a real estate.

As an example. Auctioneer from Canada won real estate – Bungalow in turkey.

User can contact auction realtors to sell item instantly with 50% discount or with some higher price.

That is not a required feature but maybe some body would prefer to exchange bungalow in turkey and get 50,000 usd in cash rather keep bungalow in other part of the earth ? sound strange, but that can open doors to all users to bid worldwide located items, lots and sell them.

As a matter of that situation, auction will open new feature - which is Black Friday. Please read more here…

Vendor Vouchers.

Unique opportunity to attract more users and consumers to company services. It is controlled category, only companies who passed compliance will be permitted to post vouchers, coupons, gift cards.

Preferred but not required denomination of
• 50 usd
• 100 usd
• 150 usd
• 200 usd
• 250 usd
• 300 usd
• 350 usd
• 400 usd
• 450 usd
• 500 usd

Above mentioned items - vouchers, coupons, gift cards, can be used within seller’s services or other services if that is permitted by seller. Valid worldwide.
It is unique savings opportunity.
Some restrictions might be applied.
Restricted to sell vouchers, coupons, gift cards - from services of other companies without written permission of company owner.
Additional exceptions for Travel Agencies ,cars, boats, other rentals.

Upcoming services and functions

• Cross Sales function
• Black Friday
• Eth Based Smart contract Bids
• Closed group Auctions
• Credit for auction.
• Auction Room
• Auction warehouse and infrastructure
• Auction mini social network.
• WeigRate wallet system.
• WeigRate Visa Card
• Folowers and follow , social aspects.

Auction Settings

There are n+1 players, indexed by i ϵ{0,1,…,n} a non-participating auctioneer (player 0) and n bidders. There is a single item for auction. Bidders have a common value v for the item5 . There is a set of potentially unbounded periods, indexed by t ϵ{0,1,2,3…} 6. Each period is characterized by a publicly-observable current leader lt ϵ{0,1,2,3…n}  with lo=0. In each period t, bidders simultaneously choose xit ϵ{Bid,Not Bid}. If any of the bidders bid, one of these bids is randomly accepted7. In this case, the corresponding bidder becomes the leader for the next period and pays a non-refundable cost c. If none of the players bids, the game ends at period t and the current leader receives the object8.

In addition to the bid costs, the winner of the auction must pay a bid amount. The bid amount starts at 0 and weakly rises by the bidding increment k ϵ ℝ+ in each period, so that the bid amount for the good at time t is tk (note that the bid amount and time are deterministically linked). Therefore, at the end of the game, the auctioneer payoff consists of the final bid amount (tk) along with the total collected bid costs (tc).

I assume that players are risk neutral and do not discount future consumption. Assume that c < v - k so that there is the potential for bidding in equilibrium. To match the empirical game, I assume that the current leader of the auction cannot place a bid9. I often refer to the net value of the good in period t as v-tk. Consequently refer to auctions with k > 0 as (k) declining-value auctions and auctions with k= 0 as constant-value auctions.

Model the game in discrete time in order to capture important qualitative characteristics that cannot be modeled in continuous time (such as the ability to bid or not bid in each individual period regardless of past choices). However, the discreteness of the game requires an additional technical assumption for declining-value auctions that mod(v-c, k)=0. If this condition is not satisfied, the game unravels and there is no equilibria in which play continues past the first period10.

 For simplicity, will focus on Markov-Perfect Equilibria. 11,12 Bidder i’s Markov strategy set consists of a bidding probability for every period given that she is a non-leader {pi0, pi1, pi2, …, pit } with pit ϵ [0,1]. Commonly make statements about the discrete hazard function, h(t,lt)≡P[xit = Not Bid]for all i ≠ lt|Reaching period t with leader lt], which is a function that maps each state (a period and potential leader) to the probability that the game ends, conditional on the state being reached. Note that h(0,0)=Πi (1-pi0) and h(t,lt)=Πi≠lͭ (1-pit).

Finally, for expositional purposes, I define two measures of profit for the auctioneer throughout the game. To understand these concepts, note that the bidder i at period t-1 is paying the auctioneer a bid cost c in exchange for a probability of h(t,i) of winning the net value of the good (v-tk) at time t. In other words, the auctioneer is selling bidder i a stochastic good with an expected value of h(t,i)(v-tk) for a price c at time t. Therefore, define the instantaneous profit of the auctioneer at time t with leader lt as π|(t,|lt) = c – h(t,lt)(v-tk) and the instantaneous percent markup as: μ(t,lt)=()·100.

5I assume that the item is worthy v<v to the auctioneer. The case in which bidders have independent private values vi~G for the item is discussed in the online appendix. As might be expected, as the distribution of private values approaches the degenerate case of one common value, the empirical predictions converge to that of the common values case.

6It is important to note that t does not represent a countdown timer or clock time. Rather, it represents a "bidding stage," which advances when any player makes a bid.

7In current real-life implementations of this auction, two simultaneous bids would be counted in (essentially) random order. Modeling this extension is difficult, especially with a large number of players, as it allows the time period to potentially "jump." Hinnosaar (2013) theoretically analyzes this change (combined with other changes to model) and finds a multiplicity of very complicated equilibria. In the online appendix, I show that the predictions of my model become much more complicated, but remain qualitatively similar when this assumption is changed in isolation.

8Note that, unlike the real-world implementation, there is no "timer" that counts down to the end of each bidding round in this model. As discussed in the online appendix, the addition of a timer complicates the model without producing any substantial insights; any equilibrium in a model with a timer can be converted into equilibrium without a timer that has the same expected outcomes and payoffs for each player.

9This assumption has no effect on the bidding equilibrium in Proposition 2 below, as the leader will not bid in equilibrium even when given the option. However, the assumption does dramatically simplify the exact form of other potential equilibria, as I discuss in the online appendix.

Equilibrium

While there are many hazard functions and strategy sets that can occur in equilibrium, I argue that it is appropriate to focus on a particular function and set (identified in Proposition 2) as these must occur in any state that is reached on the equilibrium path after period 1.

To begin the analysis, Proposition 1 notes the relatively obvious fact that no player will bid in equilibrium once the cost of a bid is greater than the net value of the good in the following period, leading the game to end with certainty in any history when this time period is reached.

Proposition 1   

If k >0, then in any Markov Perfect Equilibrium, the game never continues past period F.

That is, h(t,lt)=1 if t>F.

I refer to the set of periods that satisfy this condition as the...nal stageof the game. Note that there is no final stage of a constant-value auction, as the net value of the object does not fall and therefore this condition is never satisfied. With this constraint in mind, Proposition 2 establishes the existence of an equilibrium in which bidding occurs in each period  

Proposition 2 There exists a Markov Perfect Equilibrium in which players' strategies, the hazard rate, and auctioneer profits over time are described by

 

1                      for t=0

(A) pti ={

 

  for 0 < t ≤ F for all i

 

1                      for t>F

 

 

0                      t=0

(B) h(t,lt)={

 

  for 0 < t ≤ F for all lt

 

1                      for t>F

 

 

 

(C) π(t,lt)={

 

In an equilibrium with this hazard function, players bid symmetrically such that the hazard rate in all histories after time 0 and up to period . This hazard rate at time period t causes the expected value from bidding (and the auctioneer profit) in all histories at period t – 1 to be zero, leading players in these histories to be indifferent between bidding and not bidding. This allows players in t - 1 to use strictly mixed behavioral strategies such that the hazard rate in all histories in period  which causes the players in period t-2 to be indifferent, and so on. Crucially, in a declining-value auction, there is no positive deviation to players in period F, who are indifferent given that players in period F+ 1 bid with zero probability, (which they must do by Proposition 1).

Note that, in the hazard function in Proposition 2, h(0,0)=0 is a (arbitrarily) assumption. This choice does not change any of the results in the paper, but simply implies that some bidding always occurs in equilibrium. This is the only choice in which the auctioneer expected revenue is v, which might be considered the natural outcome in a common-value auction13.

For a constant-value auction, the strategies are equivalent to those in a symmetric discrete-time war-of-attrition (WOA) when n players remain in the game. However, the hazard rate for the WOA is higher as play only continues if more than one player bids, whereas play in a penny auction continues if any player bids .14

 Not surprisingly, there is a continuum of other equilibria in this model. In some of these equilibria, players (correctly) believe that some player will bid with very high probability in period 1 or 2, respectively, which leads them to strictly prefer to not bid in the previous period.15 Consequently, the auction always ends at period 0 or period 1. Surprisingly, Proposition 3 notes that if we ever observe bidding past period 1, we must observe the hazard rates in Proposition 2 for all periods following period 1. If additionally all n players meaningfully participate in the start of the auction (bid with some probability in the initial two periods), players must be following the individual strategies in Proposition 2 for all periods following period 1.

Proposition 3

For declining-value auctions (k >0), in any Markov Perfect Equilibrium

(A) Any observed hazard rate h(t,lt) follows Proposition 2 for t > 1.

(B) Individual strategies pit follow Proposition 2 for t >1 if pio >O and pi1 >0 for all i.

For constant-value auctions these statements are true when restricting to symmetric strategies.

To understand the intuition for statement (1) when , consider some period with  in which  As a result of this hazard rate, player must strictly prefer either to bid or not bid in period t-1. If she prefers not to bid, then will not be reached in equilibrium (and will never be observed). Alternatively, if she prefers to bid, then it must be that for any leading all players other than to strictly prefer to not bid in period . Therefore, player cannot be a non-leader in period in equilibrium, so will not be observed in equilibrium. Proposition 3 can also be interpreted as an "instantaneous zero-profit" condition on the equilibrium path. The expected hazard rate  leads to zero expected profits. If this condition is violated, players in t-1or t-2 bid in a way that keeps the state on of the equilibrium path.

Statement (2) requires the additional constraint that each player bids with some probability when t = 0 and t = 1. The constraint excludes equilibria in which one player effectively leaves the game after period 0 (leading to n-1 players in the game) and in which some player is always the leader in a specific period (allowing her strategy for that period to be or-the-equilibrium path and therefore inconsequential). For intuition as to why strategies must be symmetric, consider the case in which players i and j choose strategies such that pit ≠ pjt for some t >1 . Then, it must be that the players face different hazards as the leader in period

   , leading one of these hazards to not equals  which leads to the issues discussed above.

Finally, note that the statements when k = 0 require the additional assumption of symmetric strategies.16 Unlike in declining-value auctions, there is a somewhat complicated non-symmetric equilibrium in which three players alternatively cycle between bidding with relatively low probability and certainty. While players still expect to make zero profits from each bid over time, the hazard rate oscillates around  between periods. Choose not to focus on this type of equilibrium because this behavior requires heavy coordination among players and do not observe these oscillations empirically. Additionally, in the majority of my auction-level data and all of my bid-level data, k > 0.

10 discuss this issue in detail in the online appendix. While the equilibrium in Proposition 2 no longer exists if the condition does not hold, the strategies constitute a contemporaneous-perfect equilibrium for an extremely small E (on the order of hundredths of pennies) given the observed empirical parameters.

11A Markov-Perfect Equilibrium (Maskin and Tirole 2001) is a refinement of subgame perfection in which players are restricted to condition strategies only on payoff-relevant outcomes. In penny auctions, this removes seemingly-odd equilibria in which players coordinate bidding strategies depending on the identity of the current leader (i.e. player 10 bids if player 1 is the leader, while player 9 bids if player 2 is the leader).

12As I show in the online appendix, the statements for hazard rates all hold true when non-Markovian strategies are used.

13Furthermore, if the auctioneer values the item at less than v, then he strictly prefers that bidding occurs in period 0, while the bidders are indifferent. If the auctioneer can select the equilibrium (or repeat the auction until some bidder bids in period 0), he would euectively select the particular equilibrium in Proposition 2.

14Another intuitive explanation for this difference is that, in equilibrium, the expected total costs (the bid costs of all players) spent in each period must equal the expected total benefit (the hazard rate times the value of the good). In the penny auction, only one player ever pays a bid cost at each period, whereas in the WOA, there is a chance that more than one player must pay the bid cost. Therefore, the benefit (determined by the hazard rate) must be higher in the WOA.

15There do not exist similar asymmetric equilibria in which the auction always ends in period 2 (or later). If this occurred, all non-leaders would strictly prefer to bid in period 1. Therefore, the auction would never end in period 1. But then all bidders in period 0 could never win the auction and would strictly prefer to not bid, causing the auction to never reach period 1. "There are symmetric Markov equilibria that do not lead to the same hazard rates as those in Proposition 2. For example, consider the equilibrium in which all players always bid in odd (even) periods and never bid in even (odd) periods. In this equilibrium, the game always ends after period 0 (period 1).

16There are symmetric Markov equilibria that do not lead to the same hazard rates as those in Proposition 2. For example, consider the equilibrium in which all players always bid in odd (even) periods and never bid in even (odd) periods. In this equilibrium, the game always ends after period 0 (period 1).

The Sunk Cost Fallasy

As I will show in Section 4, the predictions of zero pro...ts from the model above are strongly empirically violated. Therefore, in this section, I preemptively present an alternative model that better matches the patterns in the data. In this simple alternative model, players suffer from a sunk cost fallacy, in that they become more willing to bid as their bid costs rise, even though these costs are sunk. This model is a simplified and modified version of the sunk-cost model introduced in Eyster (2002), in which players desire to take present decisions (continuing to invest in a bad project) to justify their past decisions (investing in the project initially).

To capture sunk costs in the most parsimonious and portable way, I simply assume that each player’s perception of the value of the good rises as she spends more money on bid costs, capturing an additional bene...t from justifying her sunk investment. Specifically, a player  who has placed bids has sunk costs  and perceives the value of the good as  defined as the sunk cost parameter. As this parameter rises, the player sunk costs cause her to bid with a higher likelyhood in the auction. If this parameter is zero, the model reverts to the standard model above.

Assume that the player is naïve about this sunk-cost effect, in the sense that she is unaware that her perception of value might change in the future and that she is unaware that other players do not necessarily share her value perception. Without the first type of naivety, players would be aware that they will bid too much in the future and consequently require a compensating premium to play the game initially, leading to zero profits for the auctioneer (and violating the empirical observations). Without the second type of naivety, each player would have very complicated higher-order beliefs, being personally unaware of her own future changes in value perception, but being aware of other players changing perceptions and being aware of other players'(correct) beliefs about her own changing perceptions. Furthermore, due to the mechanics of mixed strategy equilibria, each player (non-Markovian) bidding probability would largely be determined by the sunk costs of other players rather than her own sunk cost17. With this naivety assumption, a player simply plays the game as if the value of the good matches her perceived value, which includes a portion of her own sunk costs18

The sunk costs faced by a player at a specific time t depend on the realizations of the players own mixing decisions, the mixing decisions of the other players, and the realization of the leader selection process. Define sti as the sunk bids placed by player i at time t for a particular realization of the game. Define s  as the vector containing all of the player sunk bids and extend pti to be dependent on sti and h(t,1t) ant ℼ(t,1t) to be dependent on s. Given this adjustment, Proposition 4 mirrors Proposition 2:

Proposition 4 With sunk costs, there exists a Markov Perfect Equilibrium in which players' strategies, the hazard rate, and auctioneer profits over time are described by

 

1                               for t = 0

(A) pti (sti)={

 

  for 0 < t ≤ F for all i

 

1                             for t > F

 

 

0                      t = 0

(B)h(t,lt,s )={

 

    for 0 < t ≤ F for all lt

 

1                      for t>F

 

 

 

(C) π(t,lt,s)={

 

 If Ѳ = 0, (A), (B), and (C) matches those in Proposition 2.

These formulas depend on the specific distribution of sunk costs across the players in each game. For expositional purposes, consider the simplifying assumption that     that is, sunk costs are distributed equally across players). In this case  . While this formula will likely not be satisfied in an individual realization of the game, it is helpful in understanding the comparative statics of the hazard rate and to provide a rough interpretation of the results when the individual distribution of sunk costs is unknown.

171n a mixed strategy equilibrium, each player’ probability of bidding in the following period is chosen to make the other players indifferent between bidding in the current period. A player is still affected by her own sunk costs as she will not bid if the current bid amount is above her own perceived value.

18More specifically, following other examples of naivety in the literature, an equilibrium requires that each player actions weakly maximizes her own payoff given the players (potentially mistaken) beliefs of other players' actions. In turn, the player’ beliefs about other players' actions must constitute an equilibrium for the game that the player perceives she is playing.

 

Summary

Propositions 2 and 4 predict a variety of comparative statics about the hazard rate of the auction and bidding behavior, both with and without a sunk cost fallacy.

If players do not super from a sunk cost fallacy, the hazard rate is   and players bid with probability

  when 0 < t ≤ F, and the auctioneer profits remain constant at 0. A few comparative statics are of note. First, none of the parameters affect the auctioneer instantaneous profits, which remain at zero throughout the auction. Second, for constant-value auctions (k = 0), the hazard rate and individual bidding probabilities remain constant throughout the auction. For declining-value auctions (k >0), individuals bid less in the auction as it proceeds (and the net value of the good is falling), leading to a higher hazard rate. This erect is strengthened as the bid increment k rises. Third, as the number of players increases, each player’s equilibrium bidding probability drops, but the hazard rate and profits stay constant.19 Intuitively, the specific hazard rate in Proposition 2 can be interpreted as a zero profit condition, which must hold regardless of the number of the players. This is useful empirically, as cannot directly observe the number of players in the auction-level data. Finally, as the value of the good rises, individuals bid with higher probability and the hazard rate consequently decreases. As a result, auctions with higher values continue longer in expectation.

The final comparative static warrants a short digression. As the empirical data consist of many goods that take many values, the auctions are not predicted to share the same survival rates. This divergence creates a challenge in creating a visual representation of the predicted and empirical hazard rates. However, as I discuss in detail in the online appendix, this problem can be solved by using the concept of normalized time  t˄= . The basic intuition is that, given a constant bidding increment k, an auction with a good of value v is approximately as likely to survive past time t as an auction with a good of value 2v surviving past time 2t, with the relationship approaching equality as the length of periods approaches zero.20 That is, all auctions have approximately the same survival rates in normalized time. As a result, hazard rates in normalized time are approximately the same for these auctions, allowing auctions with different values v to be compared. Note that the use of normalized time does not equalize survival rates across auctions with different bidding increments k, which consequently must be grouped into different visual representation 21.

When players super a sunk cost fallacy, the hazard rate is i≠lt    and players bid with probability

  when 0 < t ≤ F, and the auctioneer profits are c-h(t,lts)(v-tk). There are a few important changes in the comparative statics from the standard model. For the hazard rate and bidding)probabTties, the erect is most easily seen for a constant-value auction (when the hazard is

 i≠lt   ). Rather than remaining constant over time, the hazard rate starts at the point predicted by the standard theory, but falls farther from this baseline as the auction continues. This occurs because individuals start with no sunk costs, but bid with higher probability as their personal sunk costs rise from paying for past accepted bids. This gradual deviation from the standard predictions also occurs in declining-value auctions, although it is possible that bidding probabilities rise due to the erect of the bid amount (which rises over time) overweighing the sunk-cost erect. This ambiguity does not occur when focusing on instantaneous profits (or profit margins).

191n the model, the exact number of players in the auction is common knowledge. More realistically, the number of players could be drawn from a commonly-known distribution. In this case, players will bid such that expected auctioneer profits are still zero. However, when the specific realization of the number of players is low (high), the auctioneer will make negative (positive) profits.

20For example, the probability that a constant-value auction (k= 0) with bid cost c=l and value v=100 survives to time t=50 is (1-)500~0.605, while the corresponding probability with value v=200 is (1-)100~0.606. The comparable survival probabilities for these auctions given k=1 are 0.495 and 0.497.

21It is less clear how to construct a similar normalized time measure to compare auctions with different bidding increments. Most notably, an constant-value auction (with k=0) has a non-zero survival rate at every period, while the survival rate is always zero after the final stage of a declining-value auction (k>0).